APPEARANCE, REALITY AND SKEPTICISM
It was objected in previous class that all of the examples used in
class to establish the difference between the subjective and
objective, between appearance and reality, all presuppose that we
live in a material world, that all is as it seems, and is based on
beliefs learned through the senses. This might appear to be a case
of circular reasoning (also known as the fallacy of begging the
question): proving the distinction between the subjective and
objective with references to examples which implicitly assume that
there is such a distinction. It would be like attempting to prove
the divine inspiration of the Bible by quoting 1 Timothy 3:16 “All
scripture is inspired of God…”
But why is circular reasoning bad? Isn't it because a fallacious
argument doesn’t prove anything? What does it mean to prove
something? Doesn’t it mean to establish something as true about
reality, distinct from mere belief or opinion about what could be
true or might be true? An argument goes from assumed premises to a
conclusion. The conclusion goes beyond those premises to prove
something we didn’t already know. Of course, the conclusion is only
as good as its premises. So, we need to have good reasons to think
that those premises are true. But how do we know those reasons are
any good? We will need arguments for them as well. Does this go back
infinitely? The Greek skeptic Sextus Empiricus argued that it did
and suggested that we always withhold judgement and never assent to
any proposition. But again, skepticism is a problem for knowledge,
not truth. To withhold judgement is to avoid claiming to know the
truth about reality. A skeptic might believe or suspect something is
true but despairs of ever proving it. He understands that there may
be a difference between how things appear and how they really are
and doesn’t see how we get from one to the other.
Skepticism assumes the correspondence theory of truth, the
distinction between appearance and reality. That’s part of what I
means to be a skeptic. When you raise an objection to any claim, you
are presupposing a distinction between the subjective and the
objective. You are questioning whether the statement made is
objectively true. You aren’t questioning whether it is believed by
the subject or you. You already know what you might believe about it
and, unless the other person is lying or playing Devil’s advocate,
you’re not questioning whether the other person believes what he's
saying. You are questioning whether his beliefs and statements match
up with reality. Even if you claim no one can know whether any
belief matches up with reality, you are still implicitly
assuming that there such a thing as reality as distinct from
appearances.
An alternative to the skeptic’s infinite regress is that there are
foundations to knowledge, beliefs which are self-evident,
self-justifying and axiomatic. One such belief is that a
contradiction can’t be true. You can know with certainty that it is
not both raining and not raining outside, given a precise meaning of
the term “raining.” You can know with certainty that the statement
“My twin brother helped me bake a cake that I baked all by myself”
is false. This is sometimes referred to as a priori
knowledge, knowledge which is independent of sense experience. You
do not need to investigate whether such a case exists, sniff for the
aromas of baking, look for crumbs or dirty pans hidden underneath
the sink. You can know with certainty that I didn’t bake a cake all
by myself with the help of my twin brother without even knowing
if I have a twin brother. That statement is contradictory and
could not be true in any possible world. It is logically
impossible. Basic logical truths, such as that a contradiction
can't be true, are self-evident and not provable by anything more
basic. If you don't accept that objective truth is independent of
subjective belief, then you are incapable of rational discourse. You
can't object, dispute or disagree with any statement, nor can you
concur, support or agree with any statement. You can't gather or
evaluate evidence in favor of or against any proposition being true.
All of this assumes an objective truth, facts of the matter, which
you are trying to get it using the tools of reason and evidence. Of
course, if you're a relativist who thinks that everything you
believe is already "true for you," why would you bother? Thinking is
hard work. So is research, theorizing and articulating your ideas
before a critical audience.
Some students have objected to my cake example by suggesting that
perhaps my brother both helped me and didn’t help me by playing on
the ambiguity of the term “helped.” Maybe he helped me with moral
support. However, we must remember that the Law of Excluded Middle
says that any well-qualified, meaningful proposition is
either true or false. If the term “helped” is vague, then it’s not
“well-qualified.” Only sentences with a determine meaning must have
a determinate truth value (true or false). Once we get precise on
what I mean by “helped,” you can’t play games with language and try
to make a contradiction true. When you attempt to take a vague term
and substitute one meaning in one place in an argument and another
in another place, that’s known as the fallacy of equivocation. You
are “equivocating” on a vague term and using it to mean one thing in
one place and another thing in another place in an argument. It’s
the same fallacy if you try to do it in the same sentence.
So, distinction between appearance and reality, the law of
non-contradiction, the law of excluded middle and the general method
of using logical argumentation to build systematic theories about
the world are all foundational to philosophy and any of the other
academic disciplines which emerged from it.