Most opposition to abortion relies on the premise that the fetus
is a human being, a person, from the moment of conception. The
premise is argued for, but, as I think, not well. Take, for
example, the most common argument. We are asked to notice that the
development of a human being from conception through birth into
childhood is continuous; then it is said that to draw a line, to
choose a point in this development and say "before this point the
thing is not a person, after this point it is a person" is to make
an arbitrary choice, a choice for which in the nature of things no
good reason can be given. It is concluded that the fetus is. or
anyway that we had better say it is, a person from the moment of
conception. But this conclusion does not follow. Similar things
might be said about the development of an acorn into an oak trees,
and it does not follow that acorns are oak trees, or that we had
better say they are. Arguments of this form are sometimes called
"slippery slope arguments"--the phrase is perhaps
self-explanatory--and it is dismaying that opponents of abortion
rely on them so heavily and uncritically.
I am inclined to agree, however, that the prospects for "drawing a line" in the development of the fetus look dim. I am inclined to think also that we shall probably have to agree that the fetus has already become a human person well before birth. Indeed, it comes as a surprise when one first learns how early in its life it begins to acquire human characteristics. By the tenth week, for example, it already has a face, arms and less, fingers and toes; it has internal organs, and brain activity is detectable. On the other hand, I think that the premise is false, that the fetus is not a person from the moment of conception. A newly fertilized ovum, a newly implanted clump of cells, is no more a person than an acorn is an oak tree. But I shall not discuss any of this. For it seems to me to be of great interest to ask what happens if, for the sake of argument, we allow the premise. How, precisely, are we supposed to get from there to the conclusion that abortion is morally impermissible? Opponents of abortion commonly spend most of their time establishing that the fetus is a person, and hardly anytime explaining the step from there to the impermissibility of abortion. Perhaps they think the step too simple and obvious to require much comment. Or perhaps instead they are simply being economical in argument. Many of those who defend abortion rely on the premise that the fetus is not a person, but only a bit of tissue that will become a person at birth; and why pay out more arguments than you have to? Whatever the explanation, I suggest that the step they take is neither easy nor obvious, that it calls for closer examination than it is commonly given, and that when we do give it this closer examination we shall feel inclined to reject it.
Nor do they make an exception for a case in which the mother has to spend the nine months of her pregnancy in bed. They would agree that would be a great pity, and hard on the mother; but all the same, all persons have a right to life, the fetus is a person, and so on. I suspect, in fact, that they would not make an exception for a case in which, miraculously enough, the pregnancy went on for nine years, or even the rest of the mother's life.
Let us call the view that abortion is impermissible even to
save the mother's life "the extreme view." I want to suggest
first that it does not issue from the argument I mentioned
earlier without the addition of some fairly powerful premises.
Suppose a woman has become pregnant, and now learns that she
has a cardiac condition such that she will die if she carries
the baby to term. What may be done for her? The fetus, being
to life, but as the mother is a person too, so has she a right
to life. Presumably they have an equal right to life. How is
it supposed to come out that an abortion may not be performed?
If mother and child have an equal right to life, shouldn't we
perhaps flip a coin? Or should we add to the mother's right to
life her right to decide what happens in and to her body,
which everybody seems to be ready to grant--the sum of her
rights now outweighing the fetus's right to life?
The most familiar argument here is the following. We
are told that performing the abortion would he directly killings
the child, whereas doing nothing would not be killing the mother,
but only letting her die. Moreover, in killing the child, one
would be killing an innocent person, for the child has committed
no crime, and is not aiming at his mother's death. And then there
are a variety of ways in which this might be continued. (1) But as
directly killing an innocent person is always and absolutely
impermissible, an abortion may not be performed. Or, (2) as
directly killing an innocent person is murder, and murder is
always and absolutely impermissible, an abortion may not be
performed. Or, (3) as one's duty to refrain from directly killing
an innocent person is more stringent than one's duty to keep a
person from dying, an abortion may not be performed. Or, (4) if
one's only options are directly killing an innocent person or
letting a person die, one must prefer letting the person die, and
thus an abortion may not be performed.
Some people seem to have thought that these are not further
premises which must be added if the conclusion is to be reached,
but that they follow from the very fact that an innocent person
has a right to life. But this seems to me to be a mistake, and
perhaps the simplest way to show this is to bring out that while
we must certainly grant that innocent persons have a right to
life, the theses in (1) through (4) are all false. Take (2), for
example. If directly killing an innocent person is murder, and
thus is impermissible, then the mother's directly killing the
innocent person inside her is murder, and thus is impermissible.
But it cannot seriously be thought to be murder if the mother
performs an abortion on herself to save her life. It cannot
seriously be said that she must refrain, that she must sit
passively by and wait for her death. Let us look again at the
case of you and the violinist There you are, in bed with the
violinist, and the director of the hospital says to you, "It's
all most distressing, and I deeply sympathize, but you see this
is putting an additional strain on your kidneys, and you'll be
dead within the month. But you have to stay where you are all
the same. because unplugging you would be directly killing an
innocent violinist, and that's murder, and that's
impermissible." If anything in the world is true, it is that you
do not commit murder, you do not do what is impermissible, if
you reach around to your back and unplug yourself from that
violinist to save your life.
I should perhaps stop to say explicitly that I am not claiming that people have a right to do anything whatever to save their lives. I think, rather, that there are drastic limits to the right of self-defense. If someone threatens you with death unless you torture someone else to death, I think you have not the right, even to save your life, to do so. But the case under consideration here is very different. In our case there are only two people involved, one whose life is threatened, and one who threatens it. Both are innocent: the one who is threatened is not threatened because of any fault, the one who threatens does not threaten because of any fault. For this reason we may feel that we bystanders cannot interfere. But the person threatened can.
My argument will be found unsatisfactory on two counts by many of those who want to regard abortion as morally permissible. First, while I do argue that abortion is not impermissible, I do not argue that it is always permissible. There may well be cases in which carrying the child to term requires only Minimally Decent Samaritanism of the mother, and this is a standard we must not fall below. I am inclined to think it a merit of my account precisely that it does not give a general yes or a general no. It allows for and supports our sense that, for example, a sick and desperately frightened fourteen-year-old schoolgirl, pregnant due to rape, may of course choose abortion, and that any law which rules this out is an insane law. And it also allows for and supports our sense that in other cases resort to abortion is even positively indecent. It would be indecent in the woman to request an abortion, and indecent in a doctor to perform it, if she is in her seventh month, and wants the abortion just to avoid the nuisance of postponing a trip abroad. The very fact that the arguments I have been drawing attention to treat all cases of abortion, or even all cases of abortion in which the mother's life is not at stake, as morally on a par ought to have made them suspect at the outset.
Second, while I am arguing for the permissibility of abortion in some cases, I am not arguing for the right to secure the death of the unborn child. It is easy to confuse these two things in that up to a certain point in the life of the fetus it is not able to survive outside the mother's body; hence removing it from her body guarantees its death. But they are importantly different. I have argued that you are not morally required to spend nine months in bed, sustaining the life of that violinist, but to say this is by no means to say that if, when you unplug yourself, there is a miracle and he survives, you then have a right to turn round and slit his throat. You may detach yourself even if this costs him his life; you have no right to be guaranteed his death, by some other means, if unplugging yourself does not kill him. There are some people who will feel dissatisfied by this feature of my argument. A woman may be utterly devastated by the thought of a child, a bit of herself, put out for adoption and never seen or heard of again. She may therefore want not merely that the child be detached from her, but more, that it die. Some opponents of abortion are inclined to regard this as beneath contempt--thereby showing insensitivity to what is surely a powerful source of despair. All the same, I agree that the desire for the child's death is not one which anybody may gratify, should it turn out to be possible to detach the child alive...
Discussion Questions
1. Is there a moral difference between killing and letting die?
Which is violinist case? Which is abortion?
2. In the Thomson's violinist analogy, the victim is alseep when
she is hooked up to the violinist. Is this really analogous to the
way most unwanted children are conceived? Given that there is no
consent in the violinist case, would this argument be analogous to
cases other than those involving rape?
Excerpted from Judith Jarvis Thomson, "A Defense of Abortion", Philosophy
& Public Affairs, Vol. 1, No. 1 (Fall 1971), pp. 46-66.