Common Informal Arguments
Point Out Internal Inconsistency in a
Contrary View: Because a contradiction can't be true,
showing an inconsistency can make your view look better,
although an opponent may surprise you by adjusting his
beliefs in the wrong direction. Suppose you are talking with
a conservative about the war on drugs. He claims to support
limited Constitutional government but favors federal laws
prohibiting the use of mood altering substances. You might
point out that regulation of drugs is not one of the
enumerated powers of Congress, and that the 18th Amendment
(alcohol prohibition) would have been superfluous if
Congress had a legal right to ban intoxicating substances.
Alcohol prohibition was repealed by the 21st Amendment.
Where is the amendment authorizing drug prohibition? As a
strict constitutional conservative, your conservative friend
should oppose all drug laws as unconstitutional.
Unfortunately, your friend may agree with you that the drug
war is unconstitutional but conclude that "the Constitution
isn't a suicide pact" and argue that there are some
practical considerations which trump the Constitution. But
if he does that, you might ask whether practical
considerations also trump his right to free speech, freedom
of religion or the right to keep and bear arms. Chances are,
he sees these First and Second Amendment rights as absolute.
This is inconsistent with his seeing the Ninth and Tenth
Amendment as being relative to practical concerns and may
lead him to rethink his view and to accept your argument.
Point Out Inconsistency with Accepted Facts in a Contrary
View: Here you show one of the premises supporting
your opponents' conclusion is false or that the conclusion
itself is false by pointing to evidence from authoritative
sources. Suppose an opponent argues that violent crime is on
the rise and that therefore we need stronger "tough on
crime" policies, like longer prison sentences and "stop and
frisk" policies. Pointing out FBI crime statistics which
show violent crime has gone down steadily since the
mid-1990s would be an effective way to oppose this argument.
Support Your Own View with Empirical Evidence:
When making an argument, one often appeals to empirical
facts from news reports, scholarly books or scientific
studies. Generally speaking, mainstream news reporting,
especially from a variety of sources, can be considered
generally reliable, as can the results of scientific
experiments done at universities, government research labs
or reputable private laboratories. Scholarly books and
journals by university presses or academic publishers are
also good on matters of culture or history, for example. A
series of independent news reports, scholarly works or
experiments will correct one another in case of an anomaly
or error. News organizations depend on a reputation for
reliability and scientists stake their reputations on
rigorously following protocols and safeguards to ensure
their research is sound. Journalists, scholars and
scientists also often build their reputations by finding
flaws in their competitor's work or overturning conventional
wisdom. So, while any individual news service or researcher
is fallible, she is subject to rigid professional and
institutional standards and has her work constantly
scrutinized by people looking to take her down a peg and, in
the process, improve their own stature and prestige. Thus
taken as an aggregate, news sources can be regarded as
generally reliable, especially "wire services" such as the
Associated Press, Reuters and United Press International.
However, it is also important to be on the look out for institutional
bias. Such bias pervades the media, academia and even
the sciences and will be discussed in detail later on in the
course.
Argument by Analogy: This is a very common form of
argument, especially in moral and political issues. The argument
begins with a case, sometimes hypothetical, which everyone
agrees has some quality. Next, the proponent says that this case
is like the case at hand about which he is trying to convince
you. Finally, the proponent argues that because these cases are
similar, the quality from the first case must carry over to the
second. Utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer says suppose you
are on your way to a lecture and see a child drowning in a small
pond, but stopping to save the child would ruin your new shoes
and make you late. He suggests that not saving the child under
those conditions would be monstrous. But then, he argues so is
going about our busy lives and chasing trivial pursuits while
children in the third world die of preventable diseases and
malnutrition. Just as we are obligated to help the fictitious
drowning child, we are obligated to help the "drowning" children
in impoverished countries.
Reductio Ad Absurdum: In this form of argument,
you start with your opponent's view, assume for the sake of
argument that it's true, then show it implies something totally
implausible that no one could possibly believe. For example,
suppose someone's a strong Second Amendment advocate and says
that there should be no restrictions on firearms because it's
the last line of defense against a tyrannical government. But if
you believe that, you believe that people should be able to have
weapons of the type that could defend against a military
takeover. That in turn implies that people should be able to
have fully automatic machine guns, bazookas and anti-aircraft
guns. But it's ridiculous that someone be able to walk into a
store and purchase military armaments, capable of inflicting
casualties on a massive scale, so there must be
some
restrictions on firearms, whatever the Founding Fathers'
motivations for the Second Amendment. You might see this as an
opposite approach to argument by analogy. In argument by
analogy, you start with a case that everyone agrees with and try
to show that your argument is just like it; in reductio ad
absurdum, you take your opponent's case and show that it is like
a case no one agrees with.
What is an informal fallacy?
Mistakes in reasoning can be classified into two kinds.
Formal
fallacies show a mistake which can be put in symbolic form
and are mistakes in deductive logic. Deductive arguments are
either valid or invalid, depending on whether their premises
guarantee their conclusions. We looked at two formal fallacies,
denying the antecedent and assorting the consequent, which
masquerade as the valid argument forms
modus ponens and
modus tollens.
Informal fallacies are mistakes in
inductive reasoning and also often mimic logically sound forms
of reasoning.
Appeal to authority: Appeals to
experts are appropriate, especially when giving supportive
evidence
in an argument. However, it is tempting to forgo looking at the
evidence oneself and to defer to experts. Accepting the
conclusion
of an authority without looking at any of the particulars of the
evidence is usually problematic. When considering the use of an
authoritative source of evidence in an argument, ask yourself
the following five questions: 1. Are there genuine experts in
this field? 2. Is this person or organization recognized by
others in the field as having expertise? 3. Are they an expert
on
this particular subject? 4. Is the argument relying on the
say-so of an expert when the evidence is widely available and
easily understandable to a layman? If the answer to any of these
questions is no, then appealing to such a person or organization
commits this fallacy.
For example, suppose someone says, "The Pastor at my Church says
the Bible teaches that homosexuality is a sin." You ask where
exactly in the Bible homosexuality is condemned, and your friend
says, "Oh, I don't know. It's in there some place. I trust
Pastor Bob; he has a degree from Dallas Theological Seminary."
This would be a fallacious appeal to authority because your
friend or any layperson could look up the mentions of
homosexuality in the Bible in the Old and New Testaments in an
online concordance, Bible dictionary or encyclopedia and read
them for themselves.
Is the expert in an ideologically charged field in which there
may be institutional bias or do they have an obvious vested
interest, such that their expert opinion may not be reliable?
Sometimes this is difficult to tell. Institutions are often
founded and funded in order to promulgate certain beliefs.
Funding has to come from
somewhere. Even if the original
aims are objective, a research institution may develop points of
view over time due to people hiring like-minded researchers or
where donations come from. For example, the Tobacco
Institute used to fund and release studies which coincidentally,
of course, showed that smoking or second hand smoke wasn't that
bad for you. Thinking critically means looking at such studies
with a jaundiced eye. Similarly, the meat, egg and dairy
industry funds studies that show that consuming their product is
not going to give you diabetes, heart disease or cancer. One of
the reasons to be suspicious of these studies is that there are
large bodies of studies which contradict their findings. This
isn't the case with nuts, which the evidence shows are generally
good for you. If the nut industry funds studies on the health
benefits of eating nuts, should you automatically dismiss them?
Maybe nuts
are good for you and the studies are done in
good faith and provide evidence for this. The devil is often in
the details of the study. Being cautious about industry funded
studies is wise, but if you completely dismiss a study based on
its funding source without actually looking at the evidence, you
are guilty of the
ad hominem circumstantial fallacy
below.
Another common form of appeal to authority refers to the
identity
of the individual, especially as a victim or oppressed class.
You will often hear, "As a [oppressed class], I feel that
[belief]." Often they claim to have special
moral authority
to speak on the issue. However, if you think about it logically,
the messenger of an argument is completely
irrelevant to
whether the premises are true or the reasoning is good. If you
reject my argument because of who I am, suppose I just write out
my argument and hand it to someone you sdem appropriate to
deliver it. Do my premises suddenly go from being false to true,
my reasoning from fallacious to sound? What if an argument is
written anonymously. Would you have to know who wrote it in
order to know whether it was good or bad? Of course not. Being
black, an immigrant, a woman, gay or disabled doesn't accord you
expert opinion status or give you any special authority when it
comes to speaking to contentious social issues. A person's
identity may have
rhetorical value but it has no
evidential
or
logical value. An argument stands or falls on
its merits, based on the quality of the evidence for its
premises and the strength of its logical reasoning.
Ad hominem: Literally "against the man." This is
when you attack the character or motives of the person making
the argument rather than the argument itself. The
ad
hominem abusive form is when you tar your
opponent as a nazi, racist, sexist, homophobe, xenophobe,
anti-immigrant, anti-woman, fat, ugly, stupid, etc. instead of
addressing his argument. Note that it's only an ad hominem
fallacy if you are attacking someone's irrelevant personal
characteristics as a substitute for addressing the substance of
their argument.
Ad hominem circumstantial
is when you insinuate that the person has some nefarious or
self-serving motive for believing something. It can also take
the form of requiring some sort of experiential or moral
standing in order have a view on a subject. So for example,
someone might object to a man expressing a prolife position
"because he can't get pregnant" or a person with a view on the
military who has "never served." An argument is sound or unsound
based on its contents, not on who utters it (as was seen in
fallacious appeals to authority mentioned above). To see this is
so, consider that any person making an argument could simply
have an ally of the preferred identity or circumstances utter
exactly the same words. Do the words mean something different
because they came out of someone else's mouth? Do the ideas they
have expressed change? Do their premises or reasoning become any
better or worse? Of course not. Chances are, if you think
identity matters in logical arguments, you're trying to think
with your emotions or allowing yourself to be manipulated by
rhetoric.
Guilt by Association: This fallacy is similar to the
ad
hominem attack, but instead of attacking the character of
the person making or representing an argument, you attack
someone associated with that person or attempt to connect that
person with some person or group with a bad reputation. Suppose
someone makes an argument for new and stricter gun laws, citing
the relative ease with which criminals or the mentally ill can
obtain weapons. Suppose you counter that that
Hitler was
in favor of gun control! If you did, you'd be committing the
fallacy of guilt by association. Just because Hitler favored gun
control doesn't necessarily mean it's bad. Hitler was a
vegetarian and a dog lover, too, but that doesn't imply that
vegetarianism or having a dog is bad. You brought up Hitler's
support for gun control to tarnish the idea with his bad
reputation
instead of addressing the argument. Instead
of bringing up Hitler, you could have argued that exiting laws
already bar criminals and the mentally ill from having weapons
and that what we need is better enforcement of existing laws,
not new laws restricting the rights of law-abiding citizens.
A classic example of this fallacy is the last Presidential
election, in which CNN ran story after story about marginal
Louisiana politician and former KKK Grand Wizard David Duke and
small, fringe white identity groups with little support or
influence supporting candidate Donald Trump. Liberal groups like
the Southern Poverty Law Center and various Democrat-friendly
commentators attempted to insinuate that Trump was running on a
platform of white supremacy, despite Trump's repeated statements
that he didn't have anything to do with them and repeatedly
disavowing them. If, instead of looking at his record of
involvement in civil rights issues before becoming a candidate
or his actual platform or speeches, you decided candidate Trump
was not worthy of your vote based on support from David Duke,
you would have committed the fallacy of guilt by association.
Along the same lines, the fact that serial abuser of women
Harvey Weinstein was a big Democratic donor and supporter of
Hillary Clinton is irrelevant to any of the arguments Hillary
made about women's issues on the campaign trail or whether she
is worthy of your vote, especially if it hasn't been shown she
knew of the abuse.
Jesus was criticized for eating with sinners and famously
answered, "It's not those who are healthy who need a physician,
but those who are sick." In our increasingly polarized world, we
shouldn't be afraid to engage those we disagree with in civil
dialogue. Maybe we'll convince them. Maybe we'll learn
something. Maybe they will see the light and reform. On the
other hand, if someone, closely associates with, supports and
fails to criticize someone guilty of reprehensible acts or views
or is a member of a group with an odious purpose or history,
that person may be legitimately criticized on that basis.
Tu quoque: Literally "You, too." This argument
attempts to distract from a problematic argument by pointing out
that the other side "does it, too." For example, suppose someone
brings up the topic of female "circumcision" in the Middle East
as a violation of human rights. A defender of the societies who
practice it might bring up male circumcision as practiced in the
United States. Whether male circumcision is bad has no bearing
on whether female "circumcision" is bad.
Lack of proportion: This is where two cases are compared
which are very different in degree. In the above example, the
procedure lops off the clitoris and removes or sews up the
vaginal lips. An analogous case in men would be castration or
cutting off the head of the penis. This is why this procedure is
more commonly referred to as FGM or female genital mutilation,
not circumcision. Circumcision is
an
unnecessary surgery on a child, done without consent, and
does take away some sensation, but is not comparable to FGM in
the extent of pain or damage to normal function.
Straw man: This is when you mischaracterize an opponent's
view in order to more easily attack it. This is an old medieval
combat metaphor. When practicing with weapons, instead of
fighting a real opponent, you'd attack a suit of clothes stuffed
with straw, which would represent him. Those who commit this
fallacy metaphorically impale a straw man who can't fight back
and declare victory, while ignoring their real opponent. It's
much easier to attack an absurd, exaggerated version of your
opponent's argument than their real argument.
Red herring: This is when someone brings up a seemingly
related but irrelevant topic in order to distract from the
argument at hand. The name comes from a technique used to train
hunting dogs. The dogs would be following some scent and the
trainer would drag a ripe, pungent fish across the trail in
order to to draw the dogs off the trail. Similarly, an opponent
may try to take you "into the weeds" with some other issue which
has no bearing on the subject. For example, during an abortion
protest, someone might say "Why don't you help the children who
are already born?" Whether children who are already born are
receiving sufficient care is irrelevant to the topic of whether
unborn children deserve consideration or have a right to life.
Ad Populum/Bandwagon: Everyone does or believes
something, so you should, too. For example, someone might argue
that every modern, industrialized country has socialized
medicine, so the U.S. should, too. Or she might argue that no
other modern, industrialized country has the prison population
that the U.S. has, therefore we should have fewer prisoners.
Sometimes this is used as an excuse for bad behavior. "There's
nothing wrong with taking a few office supplies from work;
everybody does it."
Slippery slope: This is the argument that a first step
will lead to a cascading series of steps culminating in some
catastrophe. For example, a person might argue that gun
registration will lead to gun confiscation and then a police
state like North Korea. Sometimes small steps do lead to
cascading negative effects. Taxes and and the creation of
government agencies are like this, as are new laws and
regulation. But in the foregoing example, a lot has to be
assumed to fill in the steps. For example, we've had gun
registration for some time but there has been no mass
confiscation, and parts of Europe, which have largely
confiscated private firearms, are not police states like North
Korea.