MORE INFORMAL FALLACIES
Hasty Generalization: Also known as over-generalization
or leaping to conclusions, this fallacy occurs when a
conclusion is drawn on based on a small or unrepresentative
number of cases. This fallacy is the basis of racial, religious
or political stereotypes. Note that this doesn't mean that no
generalizations are valid or that we can't draw general
conclusions based on a sufficient number of cases. When I was
teaching about Islam in a Religions of the Middle East class, a
student said, "They attacked us on 9/11."
Who attacked us?" I asked.
"The Muslims."
"All Muslims?"
"We should bomb them back to the Stone Age."
"There are over a billion Muslims who make up the majority
population of about 50 countries. Which one should we start
with?"
At this point the student realized she was over-generalizing. We
went on to discuss that although Al-Quaeda was an Islamic
terrorist organization, its members were a small and
unrepresentative sample of a world-wide religion.
No True Scotsman: This fallacy is committed when an ad
hoc defense of a generalization is given in order to
retain it in the face of counter-examples. It was originally
coined by British philosopher Anthony Flew:
"Imagine Hamish McDonald, a Scotsman, sitting down with his
Glasgow Morning Herald and seeing an article about how the
"Brighton Sex Maniac Strikes Again". Hamish is shocked and
declares that "No Scotsman would do such a thing." The next day
he sits down to read his Glasgow Morning Herald again; and, this
time, finds an article about an Aberdeen man whose brutal
actions make the Brighton sex maniac seem almost gentlemanly.
This fact shows that Hamish was wrong in his opinion, but is he
going to admit this? Not likely. This time he says: 'No true
Scotsman would do such a thing.'" - Antony Flew, Thinking
About Thinking: Do I Sincerely Want to Be Right? (1975),
p. 47.
Let's revisit our Islam example. When Islam scholar Carl Ernst
came to LCC, I asked him in a meeting with faculty whether he
thought our Islam Study Project should address issues the
oppression of women in certain fundamentalist Islamic societies.
He said that Islam had nothing to do with the oppression of
women. When I mentioned that women weren't allowed to drive cars
in Saudi Arabia, a theocratic Islamic state rooted in the
teachings of the Wahabi sect, he said, "I have no explanation
for psychotic behavior." The implication was that no true
Muslim would ever treat women as second class citizens. These
people just happened to be Muslims and were suffering from
pathological sexism totally unrelated to Islam. If I
were to bring up other examples of women being beaten in the
streets or jailed for not wearing the hijab (headscarf)
in Shi'a Iran, he would also say that these oppressors weren't true
Muslims either, despite their being religiously motivated and
following widespread normative institutionalized Islamic
practices.
Similarly, suppose someone claims "Islam has nothing to do with
terrorism." If you point to ISIS, Al-Quada, Hamas, the Al-Aqsa
Martyr's Brigade, Islamic Jihad, Ansar al-Sharia, Ansar
al-Islam, Boko Haram, Al-Shabaab or Hezbollah, whose ideologies
are explicitly Islamic, or a terrorist shouting "Allahu Akbar!"
while mowing down bicyclists in New York City and pledging
allegiance to the Islamic State, the retort is usually, "Well,
those aren't true Muslims." How do you know? Because no
true Muslim would commit an act of terror! This form of circular
reasoning is similar to the type employed in the fallacy of
begging the question, below. It would probably be a surprise to
all these people that they weren't "true" Muslims. Again, to say
all Muslims support terrorism is to be guilty of the
hasty generalization fallacy above, but to continue to maintain
that no Muslims support these things when faced with
empirical evidence to the contrary is to commit the no true
Scotsman fallacy.
Another example: Suppose your political science professor claims
that democracies don't start wars. Then you point out that the
first democracy, the City State of Athens, was an imperial
power, starting many wars with its neighbors, most notably
Sparta. Then he replies, "Well, Athens wasn't a true
democracy.
One more: Your gun enthusiast tells you that no supporter of the
Second Amendment supports gun registration. Then you point out
that the National Rifle Association supports it. "Well, no
true Second Amendment supporter would ever support gun
registration." The fallacious tactic is always to amend the
category just enough to maintain the generalization while
ignoring the contrary evidence, instead of admitting that the
generalization does not hold.
Begging the Question: This fallacy is also known as
circular reasoning. You commit it when you assume what
you're supposedly trying to prove. Suppose someone is trying to
convince you that the Bible is the Word of God. As evidence, he
quotes 2 Timothy 3:16, "All Scripture is inspired by God and
profitable for teaching, for reproof, for correction, for
training in righteousness." Wait a minute - that's from the
Bible! You can't quote the Bible to prove the Bible. That's
circular reasoning.
Another example: "The supposition that human beings are mere
pawns in a deterministic chess game ignores the fact of human
agency. We are not rudderless ships tossed about on a sea of
heredity and social conditioning. We have free will. Because of
this, nature and nurture can only influence, but never
determine, our actions."
In the above example, the conclusion is that determinism if
false. The "proof" offered is that we have free will (though
this is disguised in flowery language and metaphors). Obviously,
if we have free will, then determinism is false, but in order to
believe we have free will you would already have to
believe determinism is false. Free will logically implies
determinism is false. But whether or not determinism is false
what is at issue. You can't prove determinism is false by
assuming it's false.
A cute kid on the radio in a PSA on fatherhood: "There's no
other love like a Dad's love because there's nothing comparable
to it." Usually begging the question won't be as transparent as
this. Ask yourself, "What's the evidence for the conclusion?" If
that evidence looks very similar to the conclusion or wouldn't
support the conclusion without already assuming the conclusion
is true, arguing in a circle, it's probably a case of begging
the question.
Note: Sometimes people will say that a certain set of facts
"begs the question" when what they really mean is raises or
calls to mind a particular question. For example, "The idea that
we need government because people are selfish, greedy and
violent begs the question, "Aren't the politicians who run the
government human, too?'" This way of using the phrase "begging
the question" is unrelated to this fallacy and is improper
usage. Avoid it in academic papers, especially in philosophy.
Appeal to ignorance (argumentum ad ignorantiam). In this
fallacy, a person argues that a proposition is true because
there’s no evidence that it’s not true. This is an attempt to
avoid providing evidence that a claim is true by shifting the
burden to the other party. The burden of proof is always on the
person making the positive claim. In the absence of sufficient
evidence, the proper attitude toward a claim skepticism.
Non sequitur: From his Latin for "it does not follow,"
this is a fallacy in which an irrelevant reason is given for the
conclusion. You will recall that the conclusion not following
from the premises is the definition of a fallacious
argument, whether formal or informal, but, in this particular
fallacy, the problem is with the relevance of the (usually
single) premise. This irrelevancy is sometimes used as a source
of humor. For example, in a "Mama" comic, Francis asks his
mother why she has just bought a loads of junk food after
constantly nagging him about his diet. Her reply? "It was on
sale." The fact that was on sale is irrelevant to whether it is
unhealthy or inconsistent with her nagging her son about her
health. Before April 2020, the Surgeon General told people masks
weren't effective against the coronavirus because there was a
shortage and front line medical workers needed them more.
Whether there is a shortage of masks is irrelevant to whether
they are effective in protecting against the virus. The
fact that the Surgeon General wanted them reserved for
front-line workers because they were at greater risk implies
that they are effective. This seems to have been a
cynical ploy to discourage average people from buying masks to
protect themselves to ensure a sufficient number of hem for
medical workers.
Equivocation: Equivocation occurs when someone making an
argument changes the meaning of a key term in the middle of
their argument. To take another religious example, someone might
argue, "The son of God is without sin. Now the Bible says we're
all children of God, so I'm a son of God. So I can be without
sin, too!" In the first premise, the term "son of God" refers to
Jesus Christ, who in Christian theology is the one and only son
of God who died for the sins of humanity. Jesus is supposed to
have lived a perfect life in order to be a morally pure and
blameless blood atonement for our sins. The sense in which the
Bible says we are children of God is very different. We children
of God in the sense that we're all made in God's image,
descendants of Adam; there's only one sinless savior of mankind.
In the first premise, the term "son of God" refers specifically
to Jesus, "the one and only Son of God." In the second premise,
"son of God" refers to all human beings, descended from Adam,
carrying within them the stain of Adam's Original Sin in the
Garden of Eden. That's a very different meaning of "son of God."
The argument only works logically if the term means the same
thing both places. Obviously, you couldn't argue from "I am a
descendant of Adam, who was created by God but sinned and passed
down his predisposition towards sin to all future generations"
to "I can be sinless."
Suppose someone says that slavery is an important issue which
deserves more public discussion. You object that slavery
happened a long time ago and its effects have attenuated with
the generations. If that person replies, "If working for minimum
wage for the white man isn't slavery, I don't know what is!" he
would be guilty of equivocation. He has switched the meaning of
slavery from being the property of another person with no rights
and being forced to work for no pay with working for low pay,
which may be bad but is not slavery. Being a "wage-slave" is not
the same as being a literal slave. Instead of withdrawing or
modifying his original claim, he changes the meaning of a key
term mid-stream in an attempt to patch up a weakness. We would
say he is "equivocating on" the term "slavery." Often the switch
is from a literal to a more metaphorical meaning, which makes
the conclusion weaker and more plausible. Note that if the
person making the argument were to say "You're right that we
don't have literal slavery in the U.S., but the results of
slavery are still with us in the form of income inequality
between blacks and whites," that would not be equivocation. That
would directly address the counter-argument that the effects of
slavery had "attenuated" by claiming current income inequality
was the result of slavery.
The Goldilocks Fallacy: This fallacy holds that whatever
the issue, one need only identify the two extremes and stake out
the middle position as the correct one. The metaphor is from a
fairy tale about the little girl who burgled the house of three
bears. While there, she sampled three bowls of porridge waiting
on the table. One was "too hot," another was "too cold" but the
third was "just right." People who are politically uninformed
will often mouth platitudes about wanting "both sides" to "work
together" and "stop the partisan bickering," or will pride
themselves on voting on "issues" (which they often know nothing
about) and always stake out a moderate position. They have no
allegiance to party or principle, except the principle that
extremes and conflict are to be avoided at all cost and
compromise is the height of virtue. But to quote Barry
Goldwater, "Extremism in the defense of liberty is no vice, and
moderation in the defense of liberty is no virtue." What's the
middle-of-the-road position on genocide, rape, sexism, racism or
free speech? The Separate but Equal Supreme Court ruling
supporting racial segregation is a good example of where the "in
all things, moderation" approach fails.
Furthermore, how do you identify the extremes - or the middle?
Thorny social and political issues require both conceptual and
ideological thinking about the proper size, scope and role of
government as well as a careful look at the empirical evidence
for the effectiveness of particular policies. Similarly, there's
no reason to suppose that such a strategy will give you accurate
answers to questions about free will, the existence of God, the
foundation of ethics, whether religion is a positive or negative
force in the world, whether gender is biologically based or
socially constructed, whether capitalism or socialism are better
economic systems and so on. It may be in some of these cases
that a middle position is warranted, but that view needs to be
supported by evidence, not assumed, because there are many cases
where such a position is doubtful.
Post hoc/False Cause: The full name of this fallacy is
post hoc ergo proctor hoc, which is Latin for "because of
this, that." This fallacy confuses correlation with causation.
Just because one thing happened before another thing, you can't
assume that the first thing caused the second thing. You need an
explanation in terms of a causal mechanism. If you're cursed by
a Gypsy fortune-teller for making light of her powers and get
lung cancer, it would be questionable to attribute the lung
cancer to the curse. A much more likely cause would be your
habit of chain-smoking for the last 30 years. If my mother is
thinking about my father and he calls asking what's for dinner,
she may be tempted to believe they have a "psychic connection"
and that her thoughts sent out "vibrations" which caused him to
call. However, since such "psychic vibes" have never been
detected or measured, it's more likely that it's just a
coincidence. If it happens with regularity, it is likely that
there is some other cause at work. It may be that they both
begin thinking about plans for the evening at the same time,
near the end of his work day, the logical time to be thinking of
such things and making plans. Most superstitions are due to such
fallacious thinking. A black cat crosses someone's path and
something bad happens to that person. They conclude that the
black cat caused the calamity and spread the story around. Or a
person may win a game of golf wearing a particular shirt and
then lose the next game without it. He puts it back on and wins
again, concluding that wearing his "lucky shirt" improves his
game when it's just a coincidence or the benefit is entirely in
the increased self-confidence and reduced anxiety from believing
his shift gives him an edge.
To take another example, you can't necessarily give credit to or
blame the current President for the economy. For example, people
often credit Bill Clinton with the economic boom in the 90s,
ignoring the fact that he expended all his political capital on
gays in the military, increased taxes to support new government
programs, and a failed government health care initiative, paving
the way for the Republicans to get control of Congress for the
first time in 40 years in 1994. There was also the rise of the
commercial internet and spread of automation and portable
computers, the expansion of global trade and many other factors
to consider. You'd have to look at his particular policies and
see whether they were his or whether he was politically forced
into signing on to a Republican idea, as was the case with
welfare reform in 1996. It may be that the economy expanded in
spite of his policy initiatives, such as tax increases on the
investor class, not because of them. Or perhaps his policies had
little effect either way and the economy would have expanded as
it did anyway.
Note that the post hoc fallacy is when you assume, without
evidence, that one thing caused another. If someone were
to argue on basis of supply side economic principles that tax
cuts under Presidents Kennedy and Reagan led to subsequent
economic booms, that would not be the post hoc fallacy.
If you pointed to President Trump loosening the previous
administration's regulations on energy production or Trump's
efforts to keep American companies from relocating overseas and
to equalize tariffs as a reason for record low unemployment,
robust growth in manufacturing jobs and 4.2% GDP (after an
average of 1.5% throughout the 8 years of the Obama
Administration), that also would not be the post hoc
fallacy. You might disagree with the theoretical explanation
connecting these presidents' policies with subsequent economic
growth, but that's different than offering no explanation at
all. The post hoc fallacy is to merely point to
the correlation and assume causation.
Ice cream consumption is correlated with drownings, but you
wouldn't conclude that they caused drownings. Warm
summer temperatures the cause of both, of course, and are
responsible for the correlation. Similarly, it is important to
look deeply into causal explanations and determine what's
causing what and whether some third factor may be responsible
for he correlation. Suppose skiers live longer than non-skiers.
It simply may be that skiing is expensive, and more affluent
people smoke and drink less, have healthier eating habits and
can afford better medical care.
The Composition Fallacy: This fallacy occurs when you
attempt to say that because something is true of the parts, it
must also be true of the whole. This is not always the case. For
example, it may be that the payments (parts) on my student loan
are low, but that does mean that the total amount (whole) I owe
is low. To take another example, each student in the class
(parts) has a brain, but that doesn't mean that the class itself
(whole) has a brain. There is no "class brain" even though each
individual student has a brain and the class is made up of
nothing but students.
It is alleged that this fallacy is committed in the cosmological
argument for the existence of God. It claims that everything
which exists has a cause, therefore the universe itself must
have a cause. But just because each and every thing in the
universe comes from something else doesn't mean that the
universe itself, e.g. the collection of existing things, must
have a cause outside itself. It could be that things are created
and destroyed within the universe and that matter and energy are
conserved in accordance with the laws of physics. Even if every
individual thing (the parts) comes from something else doesn't
mean the collection of things (the whole) came from something
else.
The Division Fallacy: This is the opposite of the
composition fallacy, when you say that just because something is
true of the whole, it must be true of the parts. For example, my
brain has the quality of consciousness. It's composed of
billions of nerve cells. But that doesn't mean the individual
nerve cells are conscious. They're just little switches for
complex patterns of electrons and don't possess the same
qualities that my brain as a whole possesses.